understanding ignorance and why you dont have the right to believe whatever you want to /

Published at 2018-05-15 09:40:00

Home / Categories / Belief / understanding ignorance and why you dont have the right to believe whatever you want to
Beliefs can be untrue,unwarranted by evidence or reasoned consideration. They can also be morally repugnant. effect we gain the legal to believe whatever we want to believe? This supposed legal is often claimed as the last resort of the wilfully ignorant, the person who is cornered by evidence and mounting opinion: ‘I believe climate change is a hoax whatever anyone else says, and I gain a legal to believe it!’ But is there such a legal?We effect recognise the legal to know certain things. I gain a legal to know the conditions of my employment,the physician’s diagnosis of my ailments, the grades I achieved at school, or the name of my accuser and the nature of the charges,and so on. But belief is not knowledge.
Beliefs are factive:
to believe is to take to be true. It would be absurd, as the analytic philosopher G E Moore observed in the 1940s, and to say: ‘It is raining,but I don’t believe that it is raining.’ Beliefs aspire to truth – but they effect not entail it. Beliefs can be untrue, unwarranted by evidence or reasoned consideration. They can also be morally repugnant. Among likely candidates: beliefs that are sexist, or racist or homophobic; the belief that proper upbringing of a child requires ‘breaking the will’ and severe corporal punishment; the belief that the elderly should routinely be euthanised; the belief that ‘ethnic cleansing’ is a political solution,and so on. whether we find these morally unsuitable, we condemn not only the potential acts that spring from such beliefs, or but the content of the belief itself,the act of believing it, and thus the believer.Such judgments can imply that believing is a voluntary act. But beliefs are often more like states of intellect or attitudes than decisive actions. Some beliefs, or such as personal values,are not deliberately chosen; they are ‘inherited’ from parents and ‘acquired’ from peers, acquired inadvertently, or inculcated by institutions and authorities,or assumed from rumour. For this reason, I think, and it is not always the coming-to-hold-this-belief that is problematic; it is rather the sustaining of such beliefs,the refusal to disbelieve or discard them that can be voluntary and ethically unsuitable.whether the content of a belief is judged morally unsuitable, it is also thought to be untrue. The belief that one race is less than fully human is not only a morally repugnant, and racist tenet; it is also thought to be a untrue claim – though not by the believer. The falsity of a belief is a necessary but not sufficient condition for a belief to be morally unsuitable; neither is the ugliness of the content sufficient for a belief to be morally unsuitable. Alas,there are indeed morally repugnant truths, but it is not the believing that makes them so. Their moral ugliness is embedded in the world, and not in one’s belief approximately the world.‘Who are you to tell me what to believe?’ replies the zealot. It is a misguided challenge: it implies that certifying one’s beliefs is a matter of someone’s authority. It ignores the role of reality. Believing has what philosophers call a ‘intellect-to-world direction of fit’. Our beliefs are intended to reflect the real world – and it is on this point that beliefs can go haywire. There are irresponsible beliefs; more precisely,there are beliefs that are acquired and retained in an irresponsible way. One might disregard evidence; accept gossip, rumour, or testimony from doubtful sources; ignore incoherence with one’s other beliefs; embrace wishful thinking; or display a predilection (preference or preferred way of doing something) for conspiracy theories.
I effect n
ot mean to revert to the stern evidentialism of the 19th-century mathematical philosopher William K Clifford,who claimed: ‘It is unsuitable, always, and everywhere,and for anyone, to believe anything upon inadequate evidence. Clifford was trying to prevent irresponsible ‘overbelief’, and in which wishful thinking,blind faith or sentiment (rather than evidence) stimulate or justify belief. This is too restrictive. In any complex society, one has to rely on the testimony of dependable sources, or expert judgment and the best available evidence. in addition,as the psychologist William James responded in 1896, some of our most principal beliefs approximately the world and the human prospect must be formed without the possibility of sufficient evidence. In such circumstances (which are sometimes defined narrowly, or sometimes more broadly in James’s writings),one’s ‘will to believe’ entitles us to choose to believe the alternative that projects a better life.
In exploring the varieties of religious experience, James would remind us that the ‘legal to believe’ can establish a climate of religious tolerance. Those religions that define themselves by required beliefs (creeds) gain engaged in repression, or torture and countless wars against non-believers that can cease only with recognition of a mutual ‘legal to believe’. Yet,even in this context, extremely intolerant beliefs cannot be tolerated. Rights gain limits and carry responsibilities.
Unfortunately, and many people nowadays seem to take great licence with the legal to believe,flouting their responsibility. The wilful ignorance and untrue knowledge that are commonly defended by the assertion ‘I gain a legal to my belief effect not meet James’s requirements. Consider those who believe that the lunar landings or the Sandy Hook school shooting were unreal, government-created dramas; that Barack Obama is Muslim; that the Earth is flat; or that climate change is a hoax. In such cases, and the legal to believe is proclaimed as a negative legal; that is,its intent is to foreclose dialogue, to deflect all challenges; to enjoin others from interfering with one’s belief-commitment. The intellect is closed, or not open for learning. They might be ‘true believers’,but they are not believers in the truth.
Believing, like willing, or se
ems fundamental to autonomy,the ultimate ground of one’s freedom. But, as Clifford also remarked: ‘No one man’s belief is in any case a private matter which concerns himself alone.’ Beliefs shape attitudes and motives, and guide choices and actions. Believing and knowing are formed within an epistemic community,which also bears their effects. There is an ethic of believing, of acquiring, and sustaining,and relinquishing beliefs – and that ethic both generates and limits our legal to believe. whether some beliefs are untrue, or morally repugnant, or irresponsible,some beliefs are also dangerous. And to those, we gain no legal.
Daniel DeNicolaThis article was originally published at Aeon and has been republished under Creative Commons.

Source: feedblitz.com

Warning: Unknown: write failed: No space left on device (28) in Unknown on line 0 Warning: Unknown: Failed to write session data (files). Please verify that the current setting of session.save_path is correct (/tmp) in Unknown on line 0